TORTINI

For your delectation and delight, desultory dicta on the law of delicts.

Haack’s Holism vs. Too Much of Nothing

May 24th, 2012

Professor Haack has been an unflagging critic of Daubert and its progeny.  Haack’s major criticism of the Daubert and Joiner cases is based upon the notion that the Supreme Court engaged in a “divide and conquer” strategy in its evaluation of plaintiffs’ evidence, when it should have been considered the “whole gemish” (my phrase, not Haack’s).  See Susan Haack, “Warrant, Causation, and the Atomism of Evidence Law,” 5 Episteme 253, 261 (2008)[hereafter “Warrant“];  “Proving Causation: The Holism of Warrant and the Atomism of Daubert,” 4 J. Health & Biomedical Law 273, 304 (2008)[hereafter “Proving Causation“].

ATOMISM vs. HOLISM

Haack’s concern is that combined pieces of evidence, none individually sufficient to warrant an opinion of causation, may provide the warrant when considered jointly.  Haack reads Daubert to require courts to screen each piece of evidence relied upon an expert witness for reliability, a process that can interfere with discerning the conclusion most warranted by the totality or “the mosaic” of the evidence:

“The epistemological analysis offered in this paper reveals that a combination of pieces of evidence, none of them sufficient by itself to warrant a causal conclusion to the legally required degree of proof, may do so jointly. The legal analysis offered here, interlocking with this, reveals that Daubert’s requirement that courts screen each item of scientific expert testimony for reliability can actually impede the process of arriving at the conclusion most warranted by the evidence proffered.”

Warrant at 253.

But there is nothing in Daubert, or its progeny, to support this crude characterization of the judicial gatekeeping function.  Indeed, there is another federal rule of evidence, Rule 703, which is directed at screening the reasonableness of reliance upon a single piece of evidence.

Surely there are times when the single, relied upon study is one that an expert in the relevant field should and would not rely upon because of invalidity of the data, the conduct of the study, or the study’s analysis of the data.  Indeed, there may well be times, especially in litigation contexts, when an expert witness has relied upon a collection of studies, none of which is reasonably relied upon by experts in the discipline.

Rule 702, which Daubert was interpreting, was, and is, focused with an expert witness’s opinion:

A witness who is qualified as an expert by knowledge, skill, experience, training, or education may testify in the form of an opinion or otherwise if:

(a) the expert’s scientific, technical, or other specialized knowledge will help the trier of fact to understand the evidence or to determine a fact in issue;

(b) the testimony is based on sufficient facts or data;

(c) the testimony is the product of reliable principles and methods; and

(d) the expert has reliably applied the principles and methods to the facts of the case

To be sure, Chief Justice Rehnquist, in explicating why plaintiffs’ expert witnesses’ opinions must be excluded in Joiner, noted the wild, irresponsible, unwarranted inferential leaps made in interpreting specific pieces of evidence.  The plaintiffs’ expert witnesses’ interpretation of a study, involving massive injections of PCBs into the peritoneum of baby mice, with consequent alveologenic adenomas, provided an amusing example of how they, the putative experts, had outrun their scientific headlights by over-interpreting a study in a different species, at different stages of maturation, with different routes of exposure, with different, non-cancerous outcomes.  These examples were effectively aimed at showing that the overall opinion advanced by Rabbi Teitelbaum and others, on behalf of plaintiffs in Joiner, were unreliable.  Haack, however, sees a philosophical kinship with Justice Stevens, who in dissent, argued to give plaintiffs’ expert witnesses a “pass,” based upon the whole evidentiary display.  General Electric Co. v. Joiner, 522 U.S. 136, 153 (1997) (Justice Stevens, dissenting) (“It is not intrinsically ‘unscientific’ for experienced professionals to arrive at a conclusion by weighing all available evidence.”). The problem, of course, is that sometimes “all available evidence” includes a good deal of junk, irrelevant, or invalid studies.  Sometimes “all available evidence” is just too much of nothing.

Perhaps Professor Haack was hurt that she was not cited by Justice Blackmun in Daubert, along with Popper and Hempel.  Haack has written widely on philosophy of science, and on epistemology, and she clearly believes her theory of knowledge would provide a better guide to the difficult task of screening expert witness opinions.

When Professor Haacks describes the “degree to which evidence warrants a conclusion,” she identifies three factors, which in part, require assessment of the strength of individual studies:

(i) how strong the connection is between the evidence and the conclusion (supportiveness);

(ii) how solid each of the elements of the evidence is, independent of the conclusion (independent security); and

(iii) how much of the relevant evidence the evidence includes (comprehensiveness).

Warrant at 258

Of course, supportiveness includes interconnectedness, but nothing in her theory of “warrant” excuses or omits rigorous examination of individual pieces of evidence in assessing a causal claim.

DONE WRONG

Haack seems enamored of the holistic approach taken by Dr. Done, plaintiffs’ expert witness in the Bendectin litigation. Done tried to justify his causal opinions based upon the entire “mosaic” of evidence. See, e.g., Oxendine v. Merrell Dow Pharms. Inc, 506 A.2d 1100, 1108 (D.C 1986)(“[Dr. Done] conceded his inability to conclude that Bendectin is a teratogen based on any of the individual studies which he discussed, but he also made quite clear that all these studies must be viewed together, and that, so viewed, they supplied his conclusion”).

Haack tilts at windmills by trying to argue the plausibility of Dr. Done’s mosaic in some of the Bendectin cases.  She rightly points out that Done challenged the internal and external validity of the defendant’s studies.  Such challenges to the validity of either side’s studies are a legitimate part of scientific discourse, and certainly a part of legal argumentation, but attacks on validity of null studies are not affirmative evidence of an association.  Haack correctly notes that “absence of evidence that p is just that — an absence of evidence of evidence; it is not evidence that not-p.”  Proving Causation at 300.  But the same point holds with respect to Done’s challenges to Merrill Dow’s studies.  If those studies are invalid, and Merrill Dow lacks evidence that “not-p,” this lack is not evidence for Done in favor of p.

Given the lack of supporting epidemiologic data in many studies, and the weak and invalid data relied upon, Done’s causal claims were suspect and have come to be discredited.  Professor Ronald Allen notes that invoking the Bendectin litigation in defense of a “mosaic theory” of evidentiary admissibility is a rather peculiar move for epistemology:

“[T]here were many such hints of risk at the time of litigation, but it is now generally accepted that those slight hints were statistical aberrations or the results of poorly conducted studies.76 Bendectin is still prescribed in many places in the world, including Europe, is endorsed by the World Health Organization as safe, and has been vindicated by meta-analyses and the support of a number of epidemiological studies.77 Given the weight of evidence in favor of Bendectin’s safety, it seems peculiar to argue for mosaic evidence from a case in which it would have plainly been misleading.”

Ronald J. Allen & Esfand Nafisi, “Daubert and its Discontents,” 76 Brooklyn L. Rev. 131, 148 (2010).

Screening each item of “expert evidence” for reliability may deprive the judge of “the mosaic,” but that is not all that the judicial gatekeepers were doing in Bendectin or other Rule 702 cases.   It is all well and good to speak metaphorically about mosaics, but the metaphor and its limits were long ago acknowledged in the philosophy of science.  The suggestion that scraps of evidence from different kinds of scientific studies can establish scientific knowledge was rejected by the great mathematician, physicist, and philosopher of science, Henri Poincaré:

“[O]n fait la science avec des faits comme une maison avec des pierres; mais une accumulation de faits n’est pas plus une science qu’un tas de pierres n’est une maison.”

Jules Henri Poincaré, La Science et l’Hypothèse (1905) (chapter 9, Les Hypothèses en Physique)( “Science is built up with facts, as a house is with stones. But a collection of facts is no more a science than a heap of stones is a house.”).  Poincaré’s metaphor is more powerful than Haack’s and Done’s “mosaic” because it acknowledges that interlocking pieces of evidence may cohere as a building, or they may be no more than a pile of rubble.  Poorly constructed walls may soon revert to the pile of stones from which they came.  Much more is required than simply invoking the “mosaic” theory to bless this mess as a “warranted” claim to knowledge.

Haack’s point about aggregation of evidence is, at one level, unexceptionable.  Surely, the individual pieces of evidence, each inconclusive alone, may be powerful when combined.  An easy example is a series of studies, each with a non-statistically significant result of finding more disease than expected.  None of the studies alone can rule out chance as an explanation, and the defense might be tempted to argue that it is inappropriate to rely upon any of the studies because none is statistically significant.

The defense argument may be wrong in cases in which a valid meta-analysis can be deployed to combine the results into a summary estimate of association.  If a meta-analysis is appropriate, the studies collectively may allow the exclusion of chance as an explanation for the disparity from expected rates of disease in the observed populations.  [Haack misinterprets study “effect size” to be relevant to ruling out chance as explanation for the increased rate of the outcome of interest. Proving Causation at 297.]

The availability of meta-analysis, in some cases, does not mean that hand waving about the “combined evidence” or “mosaics” automatically supports admissibility of the causal opinion.  The gatekeeper would still have to contend with the criteria of validity for meta-analysis, as well as with bias and confounding in the underlying studies.

NECESSITY OF JUDGMENT

Of course, unlike the meta-analysis example, most instances of evaluating an entire evidentiary display are not quantitative exercises.  Haack is troubled by the qualitative, continuous nature of reliability, but the “in or out” aspect of ruling on expert witness opinion admissibility.  Warrant at 262.  The continuous nature of a reliability spectrum, however, does not preclude the practical need for a decision.  We distinguish young from old people, although we age imperceptibly by units of time that are continuous and capable of being specified with increasingly small magnitudes.  Differences of opinions or close cases are likely, but decisions are made in scientific contexts all the time.

FAGGOT FALLACY

Although Haack criticizes defendants for beguiling courts with the claimed “faggot fallacy,” she occasionally, acknowledges that there simply is not sufficient valid evidence to support a conclusion.  Indeed, she makes the case for why, in legal contexts, we will frequently be dealing with “unwarranted” claims:

“Against this background, it isn’t hard to see why the legal system has had difficulties in handling scientific testimony. It often calls on the weaker areas of science and/or on weak or marginal scientists in an area; moreover, its adversarial character may mean that even solid scientific information gets distorted; it may suppress or sequester relevant data; it may demand scientific answers when none are yet well-warranted; it may fumble in applying general scientific findings to specific cases; and it may fail to adapt appropriately as a relevant scientific field progresses.”

Susan Haack, ” Of Truth, in Science and in Law,” 73 Brooklyn L. Rev. 985, 1000 (2008).  It is difficult to imagine a more vigorous call for, and defense of, judicial gatekeeping of expert witness opinion testimony.

Haack seems to object to the scope and intensity of federal judicial gatekeeping, but her characterization of the legal context should awaken her to the need to resist admitting opinions on scientific issues when “none are yet well-warranted.” Id. at 1004 (noting that “the legal system quite often want[s] scientific answers when no warranted answers are available).  The legal system, however, does not “want” unwarranted “scientific” answers; only an interested party on one side or the other wants such a thing.  The legal systems wants a procedure for ensuring rejection of unwarranted claims, which may be passed off as properly warranted, due to the lack of sophistication of the intended audience.

TOO MUCH OF NOTHING

Despite her flirtation with Dr. Done’s holistic medicine, Haack acknowledges that sometimes a study or an entire line of studies is simply not valid, and they should not be part of the “gemish.”  For instance, in the context of meta-analysis, which requires pre-specified inclusionary and exclusionary criteria for studies, Haack acknowledges that a “well-designed and well-conducted meta-analysis” will include a determination “which studies are good enough to be included … and which are best disregarded.”  Proving Causation at 286.  Exactly correct.  Sometimes we simply must drill down to the individual study, and what we find may require us to exclude it from the meta-analysis.  The same could be said of any study that is excluded by appropriate exclusionary criteria.

Elsewhere, Haack acknowledges myriad considerations of validity or invalidity, which must be weighed as part of the gemish:

“The effects of S on animals may be different from its effects on humans. The effects of b when combined with a and c may be different from its effects alone, or when combined with x and/or y.52 Even an epidemiological study showing a strong association between exposure to S and elevated risk of D would be insufficient by itself: it might be poorly-designed and/or poorly-executed, for example (moreover, what constitutes a well-designed study – e.g., what controls are needed – itself depends on further information about the kinds of factor that might be relevant). And even an excellent epidemiological study may pick up, not a causal connection between S and D, but an underlying cause both of exposure to S and of D; or possibly reflect the fact that people in the very early stages of D develop a craving for S. Nor is evidence that the incidence of D fell after S was withdrawn sufficient by itself to establish causation – perhaps vigilance in reporting D was relaxed after S was withdrawn, or perhaps exposure to x, y, z was also reduced, and one or all of these cause D, etc.53

Proving Causation at 288.  These are precisely the sorts of reasons that make gatekeeping of expert witness opinions an important part of the judicial process in litigation.

RATS TO YOU

Similarly, Haack acknowledges that animal studies may be quite irrelevant to the issue at hand:

“The elements of E will also interlock more tightly the more physiologically similar the animals used in any animal studies are to human beings. The results of tests on hummingbirds or frogs would barely engage at all with epidemiological evidence of risk to humans, while the results of tests on mice, rats, guinea-pigs, or rabbits would interlock more tightly with such evidence, and the results of tests on primates more tightly yet. Of course, “similar” has to be understood as elliptical for “similar in the relevant respects;” and which respects are relevant may depend on, among other things, the mode of exposure: if humans are exposed to S by inhalation, for example, it matters whether the laboratory animals used have a similar rate of respiration. (Sometimes animal studies may themselves reveal relevant differences; for example, the rats on which Thalidomide was tested were immune to the sedative effect it had on humans; which should have raised suspicions that rats were a poor choice of experimental animal for this drug.)55 Again, the results of animal tests will interlock more tightly with evidence of risk to humans the more similar the dose of S involved. (One weakness of Joiner’s expert testimony was that the animal studies relied on involved injecting massive doses of PCBs into a baby mouse’s peritoneum, whereas Mr. Joiner had been exposed to much smaller doses when the contaminated insulating oil splashed onto his skin and into his eyes.)56 The timing of the exposure may also matter, e.g., when the claim at issue is that a pregnant woman’s being exposed to S causes this or that specific type of damage to the fetus.”

Proving Causation at 290.

WEIGHT OF THE EVIDENCE (WOE)

Just as she criticizes General Electric for advancing the “faggot fallacy” in Joiner, Haack criticizes the plaintiffs’ appeal to “weight of evidence methodology,” as misleadingly suggesting “that there is anything like an algorithm or protocol, some effective, mechanical procedure for calculating the combined worth of evidence.”  Proving Causation at 293.

INFERENCE  TO BEST EXPLANATION

Professor Haack cautiously evaluates the glib invocation of “inference to the best explanation” as a substitute for actual warrant of a claim to knowledge.  Haack acknowledges the obvious: the legal system is often confronted with claims lacking sufficient warrant.  She appropriately refuses to permit such claims to be dressed up as scientific conclusions by invoking their plausibility:

“Can we infer from the fact that the causes of D are as yet unknown, and that a plaintiff developed D after being exposed to S, that it was this exposure that caused Ms. X’s or Mr. Y’s D?102  No. Such evidence would certainly give us reason to look into the possibility that S is the, or a, cause of D. But loose talk of ‘inference to the best explanation’ disguises the fact that what presently seems like the most plausible explanation may not really be so – indeed, may not really be an explanation at all. We may not know all the potential causes of D, or even which other candidate-explanations we would be wise to investigate.”

Proving Causation at 305.  See also Warrant at 261 (invoking the epistemic category of Rumsfeld’s “known unknowns” and “unknown unknowns” to describe a recurring situation in law’s treatment of scientific claims)(U.S. Sec’y of Defense Donald Rumsfeld: “[T]here are known knowns; there are things we know we know. We also know there are known unknowns; that is to say we know there are some things we do not know. But there are also unknown unknowns – there are things we do not know we don’t know. (Feb. 12, 2002)).

It is easy to see why the folks at SKAPP are so fond of Professor Haack’s writings, and why they have invited her to their conferences and meetings.  She has written close to a dozen articles critical of Daubert, each repeating the same mistaken criticisms of the gatekeeping process.  She has provided SKAPP and its plaintiffs’ lawyer sponsors with sound bites to throw at impressionable judges about the epistemological weakness of Daubert and its progeny.  In advancing this critique and SKAPP’s propaganda purposes, Professor Haack has misunderstood the gatekeeping enterprise.  She has, however, correctly identified the gatekeeping process as an exercise in determining whether an opinion possesses sufficient epistemic warrant.  Despite her enthusiasm for the dubious claims of Dr. Done, Haack acknowledges that “warrant” requires close attention to the internal and external validity of studies, and to rigorous analysis of a body of evidence.  Haack’s own epistemic analysis would be hugely improved and advanced by focusing on how the mosaic theory, or WOE, failed to hold up in some of the more egregious, pathological claims of health “effects” — Bendectin, silicone, electro-magnetic frequency, asbestos and colorectal cancer, etc.

The Pennsylvania Supreme Court Rejects “Every Exposure is Substantial” Mantra

May 23rd, 2012

Over two years ago, I wrote about a curious decision by the Pennsylvania Superior Court, in Betz v. Pneumo Abex LLC, 998 A.2d 962 (Pa. Super. 2010) (en banc). In Betz, the Superior Court reversed an Alleghany County Court of Common Pleas judge’s Frye ruling, in an asbestos mesothelioma case, that an expert witness’s opinion that each exposure had been a “substantial contributing factor” was both novel and not generally accepted. In re Toxic Substance Cases, No. A.D. 03-319, slip op., 2006 WL 2404008 (C.P. Allegheny, Aug. 17, 2006). What was remarkable was that the majority of the en banc Superior Court treated the science and the record so cavalierly, and treated the law even more so. SeeBetz v. Pneumo Abex: the Recrudescence of Ferebee in Pennsylvania” (May 5th, 2010); and “The Betz Evidence Rule” (May 6th, 2010).

Today, mirabile dictu, the Pennsylvania Supreme Court unanimously reversed the Superior Court’s errant opinion.  (Justice Melvin did not, of course, participate.) The Supreme Court held that the trial judge, Judge Colville, did not abuse his discretion in conducting a Frye hearing or in ruling that the plaintiffs’ expert witness’s opinion, that every fiber contributes substantially to plaintiff’s mesothelioma, was both novel and not “generally accepted.”

The Supreme Court remanded to the Superior Court for a decision on unspecified, remaining issues. The Court’s 53 page opinion carefully dissects the ipse dixit nature of plaintiffs’ expert witness’s specific causation opinion, and essentially concludes that there was no science in it all.

On the Importance of Showing Relative Risks Greater Than Two – Haack’s Arguments

May 23rd, 2012

Professor Susan Haack has set out, repeatedly, to criticize the judicial requirement of relative risks greater than two to support findings that exposure to a substance, process, or medication was a specific cause of a plaintiff’s injury.  If for no other reason than the frequency with which Haack has published on this same issue, her views are worth examining more closely.

Haack’s argument, typically, proceeds along the lines that requiring a relative risk greater than two (RR > 2) is improper because a RR > 2 is neither necessary nor sufficient for finding specific causation.  See, e.g., Susan Haack, “Warrant, Causation, and the Atomism of Evidence Law,” 5 Episteme 253, 261 (2008)[hereafter “Warrant“];  “Proving Causation: The Holism of Warrant and the Atomism of Daubert,” 4 J. Health & Biomedical Law 273, 304 (2008)[hereafter “Proving Causation“].

Unlike the more sophisticated reasons offered by Professor Sander Greenland, Professor Haack’s reasoning fails to understand both the law and the science.

Haack:  RR > 2 Not Sufficient

Haack argues that RR > 2 is not sufficient for two reasons:

“Epidemiological evidence of a doubling of risk is not sufficient for specific causation: first, because if the study showing a doubling of risk is poorly-designed or poorly-executed, we would have only a low epistemological likelihood of a greater than 50% statistical probability; and second, because even a well-designed and well-conducted study might also show that those subjects who develop D [some claimed causally related disease] when exposed to S [some substance] have some characteristic in common – older patients rather than younger, perhaps, or women rather than men, or the sedentary rather than the active – and our plaintiff might be an elderly, sedentary female.”

Proving Causation at 304 (emphasis added).

The first argument is largely irrelevant to the legal context in which the RR > 2 rationale arises.  Typically, plaintiffs assert general and specific causation on the basis of a complex evidentiary display.  This display includes evidence of an epidemiologic association, but the magnitude of the association is weak, with RR > 1, but < 2.  Thus the defendants challenge the attributability in the plaintiff’s individual case.  The overall evidentiary display may or may not support general causation, but even if general causation were conceded, specific causation would remain as independent factual issue.  Haack’s first “argument” is that the RR > 2 argument is insufficient because the study with RR > 2 may lack internal validity on grounds that it was poorly designed, poorly conducted, or poorly analyzed.  True, true, but immaterial.  On motions for summary judgment or directed verdict, the trial court would resolve any factual issues about disputed validity in favor of the non-moving party.  The defense may have better studies that show the RR =1, but these would not factor in the decision to grant or refuse the motion.  (If the defense can show that the plaintiffs’ studies with RR > 2 are fatally flawed, then the plaintiffs might be relegated to their studies with lower risk.)

Haack’s second reason appears to go to external validity.  She suggests that a study at issue may be in a population that shares key risk factors with the plaintiff.  Why this similarity would suggest that RR > 2 is not sufficient is quite mysterious.  External validity would support the applicability of the study, with its RR > 2, not militate against its sufficiency.  If the “characteristic in common” is the basis for an interaction with the exposure to S, then we would expect that to be shown by the data in the study; it would not, and should not, be a matter of conjecture or speculation.

Haack:  RR > 2 Not Necessary

Similarly, Haack argues that RR > 2 is not necessary for two reasons:

“And epidemiological evidence of a doubling of risk is not necessary for specific causation, either: first, because studies that fail to show a doubling of risk may be flawed – for example, by failing to take account of the period of pregnancy in which subjects are exposed to S, or by failing to take account of the fact that subjects are included who may have been exposed to S in cold medication or sleep-aids; 99 and second, because even a good epidemiological study indicating to a high degree of epistemic likelihood that there is a doubling of risk may also indicate that those subjects who develop D have some characteristic (such as being over 50 or sedentary or subject to allergies or whatever) that this plaintiff lacks.100

Proving Causation at 304 (emphasis added).

Again, Haack’s reasoning is nothing other than an invitation to speculate.  Sure, studies with RR < 2 may be flawed, but the existence of flaws in the studies is hardly a warrant for the true RR > 2.  The evidence is the thing; and she is quick to point out elsewhere:  absence of evidence is not evidence of absence.  And so a flawed study is not particularly probative of anything; it cannot be made into affirmative evidence of the opposite result by the existence of a flaw.  Haack seems to be suggesting that the studies at issue, with RR < 2, may be biased low by misclassification or other systemic bias.  Again, true, true, and immaterial.  An epidemiologic study may suffer bias (or not), but if it does, the usual path is conduct the study again without the previous bias.  Sometimes the data may be re-analyzed, and the march of progress is in the direction of having underlying data accessible to permit some degree of re-analysis.  In any event, cases with RR < 2, or RR = 2, are not transformed into cases of RR > 2, solely by hand waving or speculation over the existence of potential bias.  The existence and direction of the bias remains something that must be shown by competent evidence.

As for the second argument, again, Haack invokes external invalidity as a possible reason that a RR > 2 does not necessarily require a finding for plaintiff.  The plaintiff may be sufficiently different from study participants such that the RR > 2 is not relevant.  This argument hardly undermines a requirement for a RR > 2, based upon a relevant study.

These arguments are repeated virtually verbatim in Proving Causation, where Haack asserts for the same reasons that a RR > 2 is neither necessary nor sufficient for showing specific causation.  Proving Causation at 261.

In an unpublished paper, which Haack has presented several times over the last few years, she has criticized the RR >2 argument as an example of flawed “probabilism” in the law.  Susan Haack, “Risky Business:  Statistical Proof of Individual Causation,” in Jordi Ferrer Beltrán, ed., Casuación y atribución de responsibilidad (Madrid: Marcial Pons, forthcoming)[hereafter Risky Business]; Presentation at the Hastings Law School (Jan. 20, 2012);  Presentation at University of Girona (May 24, 2011)

While there is some merit to Haack’s criticisms of probabilism, they miss the important point, which is that sometimes probabilistic inference is all there is.  Haack cites the New Jersey Supreme Court’s decision in Landrigan as supporting her notion that “other evidence,” presumably particularistic, plaintiff-specific evidence, plus a RR < 2 will suffice:

“The following year (1992), in Landrigan, the Supreme Court of New Jersey briskly observed that ‘a relative risk of 2.0 is not so much a password to a finding of causation as one piece of evidence among others’.”

Risky Business at 22 (citing and quoting Landrigan v. Celotex Corp., 127 N.J. 404, 419, 605 A.2d 1079 (1992)).

Haack, however, advances a common, but mistaken reading of Landrigan, where the Court blurred the distinction between sufficiency and admissibility of expert witness opinion on specific causation.  Landrigan, and another case, Caterinicchio v. Pittsburgh Corning Corp., 127 N.J. 428, 605 A.2d 1092 (1992), were both tried to juries, about the same time, in different counties in New Jersey.  (My former partner Terri Keeley tried Landrigan; I tried Caterinicchio.)  There was no motion to exclude expert witness testimony in either case; nor was there a motion for summary judgment ever lodged pre-trial.  Both cases involved motions for directed verdict, in which the defense invited the trial courts to accept the plaintiffs’ expert witnesses’ opinions, arguendo, and to focus on the inference of specific causation, which was drawn upon the assertion that both Mr. Landrigan and Mr. Caterinicchio had an increased risk of colorectal cancer as a result of their occupational asbestos exposure.  Admissibility was never in issue.

There were no valid biomarkers, no “fingerprints” of causation; no evidence of either plaintiff’s individual, special vulnerability.  The plaintiffs had put in their cases and rested; the trial courts were required to assume that the facts were as presented by the plaintiffs.  All the plaintiffs had offered, however, of any possible relevance, was a relative risk statistic. The trial courts in both cases granted the directed verdicts, and separate panels of the New Jersey Appellate Division affirmed.  Riding roughshod over the evidence, the New Jersey Supreme Court granted certification in both cases, and reversed and remanded for new trials.

Haack does an admirable job of echoing the speculation advanced by plaintiffs on appeal, in both Landrigan and Caterinicchio.  She speculates that the plaintiffs may have had greater than average exposure, or that they were somehow more vulnerable than the average exposed person in the relevant studies.

To paraphrase a Rumsfeldian bon mot:  The litigants must go to trial with the evidence that they have.

Both cases were remanded for new trials.  What is often not reported or discussed in connection with these two cases is that plaintiffs’ counsel dismissed Landrigan before proceeding with a new trial.  Caterinicchio was indeed retried — to a defense verdict.

International Labor Organization – What Really Matters in Occupational Safety

May 20th, 2012

Created in 1919, the International Labour Organization (ILO) is now part of the United Nations.  The ILO, with its motto, “Promoting Jobs, Protecting People,” exists as a forum for governments, employers, and workers, to shape policies and programs to advance safe, dignified work.

The ILO has been involved in many aspects of protecting workers against the dust diseases of the lungs.  Every United States lawyer who litigates pneumoconiosis claims is, of necessity, familiar with the ILO’s system for standardizing the classification and interpretation of plain film chest radiographs for the pneumoconioses.  Last year, in conjunction with the National Institute of Occupational Safety and Health (NIOSH), the ILO reissued its long-awaited guidelines for digital radiographs.  Guidelines for the use of the ILO International Classification of Radiographs of Pneumoconioses, revised edition 2011 (Nov. 17, 2011).

The ILO system for classifying chest radiographs is used around the world for health surveillance, epidemiologic studies, and in some places, for assessing extent of pneumoconiotic disease and compensation for silicosis, asbestos-related diseases and coal workers’ pneumoconiosis. See ILO fact sheet about the 2011 edition of the classification system.

The ILO standard radiographic images are now available in DICOM Format on DVD from the ILO.  In January 2012, NIOSH published a “Notice of Proposed Rulemaking – Amendments to Specifications for Medical Examinations of Underground Coal Miners” to modify regulations of the Coal Worker’s Health Surveillance Program (CWHSP), to retain the use of plain film, while permitting the use of digital radiography for the assessment of coal worker’s pneumoconiosis.

* * *

The ILO has done important work in other areas as well.  If you are looking for a single publication that captures the key principles of providing a safe workplace, you would be hard pressed to find a better source than the ILO’s text on occupational safety and health. Benjamin Alli, Fundamental principles of occupational health and safety (2d ed. 2008).    The first edition, from 2001, is available for free from the ILO’s website. Benjamin Alli, Fundamental principles of occupational health and safety (1st ed. 2001).

The ILO describes the text as

“useful for legislators and labour inspectors, those involved in policy-making (governments, and employers’ and workers’ organizations) and those within enterprises who are concerned with the practical implementation of measures to promote and protect the safety and health of workers (managers, supervisors, workers’ representatives), as well as academic institutions.”

What is remarkable about the ILO text is the even-handedness in which it describes the respective responsibilities of the employers and workers for the promotion and preservation of workers’ health.  The duties of employers are described as including the duty to:

  • “inform  the  workers  of  all  the known hazards associated with their work, the health risks involved and the relevant preventive and protective measures;
  • take appropriate  measures  to eliminate or minimize the risks resulting from exposure to those hazards;
  • provide  workers  with  suitable protective equipment, clothing and  other  facilities  where  adequate protection against risk of accident or injury to health, including  exposure  to  adverse conditions, cannot be ensured by other means… .”

Id. at page 95.   In practical terms, the ILO specifies the “work practices and organizational methods” to reduce or eliminate safety and health hazards.  Personal protective equipment, such as respirators, is a last resort:

“When none of the above approaches is feasible, or when the degree of safety achieved is considered inadequate, the only solution is to provide exposed persons with suitable personal protective equipment and protective clothing. This is the final line of defence and should be used only as a last resort, since it entails reliance on active cooperation and compliance by the workers. Moreover, such equipment may be heavy, cumbersome and uncomfortable, and may restrict movement.

Employers should consult workers or their representatives on suitable personal protective equipment and clothing, having regard to the type of work and risks. Furthermore, when hazards cannot be otherwise prevented or controlled,  employers should provide and maintain such equipment and clothing as are reasonably necessary, without cost to the workers. The employer should provide the workers with the appropriate means to enable them to use the individual protective equipment. Indeed, the employer has a duty to ensure its proper use. Protective equipment and clothing should comply with the standards set by the competent authority and take ergonomic principles into account. Workers have the obligation to make proper use of and take good care of the personal protective equipment and protective clothing provided for their use.”

Id. at 97.

Remarkably, what is absent from the ILO text is any rhetoric or rationale in support of warnings on products from remote vendors.  Judges and legislators might well take note that the dissemination of information about hazards in a workplace is so dependent upon employers in the first instance, and workers in the next, that it will be a rare case when a supplier of a raw material or commodity will actually have the opportunity to play a substantial role in causing a chronic over-exposure occupational disease.  The focus of the American law on warnings from a remote supplier is an anomaly created by the legislative immunity accorded employers in the tort system.

Exposure, Epidemiology, and External Validity under Rule 702

May 14th, 2012

Sometimes legal counsel take positions in court determined solely by the expediency of what expert witnesses are available, and what opinions are held by those witnesses.

Back in the early days of the asbestos litigation in Philadelphia, a hotbed of early asbestos litigation, plaintiffs and defendants each identified a pool of available expert witnesses on lung diseases.  Each side found witnesses who held views on important issues, such as whether asbestos caused lung cancer, with or without pre-existing asbestosis, whether all types of asbestos caused mesothelioma, whether asbestos caused gastrointestinal cancers, and whether “each and every exposure was a substantial factor” in producing an asbestos-related disease.  Some expert witnesses adopted opinions as a matter of convenience and malleability, but most witnesses expressed sincerely held opinions.  Either way, each expert witness active in the asbestos litigation, came to be seen as a partisan of one side.  Because of the volume of cases, there was the opportunity to be engaged in a large number of cases, and to earn sizable fees as an expert witness.  Both side’s expert witnesses struggled to avoid being labeled hired guns.

A few expert witnesses, eager to avoid being locked in as either a “plaintiff’s” or a “defendant’s” expert witness, with perhaps some damage to their professional reputations, balanced their views in a way to avoid being classified as working exclusively for one side or the other.  The late Paul Epstein, MD, adopted this strategy to great effect.  Dr. Epstein had excellent credentials, and he was an excellent physician.  He was on the faculty at the University of Pennsylvania, and he was a leader in the American College of Physicians, where he was the deputy editor of the Annals of Internal Medicine.  Dr. Epstein exemplified gravitas and learning.  He was not, however, above adopting views in such a way as to balance out his commitments to both the plaintiffs’ and defense bars.  By doing so, Dr. Epstein made himself invaluable to both sides, and he made aggressive cross-examination difficult, if not impossible, when he testified.  I suspect his positions had this strategic goal.

In his first testimonies, in the late 1970’s and early 1980’s, Dr. Epstein expressed the view that asbestos exposure caused parietal pleural plaques, but these plaques rarely interfered with respiration.  Pleural plaques did not cause impairment or disability, and thus they were not an “injury.”  Dr. Epstein’s views were very helpful in obtaining defense verdicts in cases of disputed pleural thickening or plaques, and they led to his being much sought after by defense counsel for their independent medical examinations.  Dr. Epstein also strongly believed, based upon the epidemiologic evidence, that asbestos did not cause gastrointestinal or laryngeal cancer.

Dr. Epstein was wary of being labeled a “defendants’ expert” in the asbestos litigation, especially given the social opprobrium that attached to working for the “asbestos industry.”  And so, by the mid-1980’s, Dr. Epstein surprised the defense bar by showing up in a plaintiff’s lung cancer case, without underlying asbestosis.  Dr. Epstein took the position that if the plaintiff worked around asbestos, and later developed lung cancer, then asbestos caused his lung cancer, and “each and every exposure to asbestos” contributed substantially to the outcome.  Risk was causation; ipse dixit.  Dr. Epstein recited the Selikoff multiplicative “synergy” theory, with relative risks of 5 (for non-smoking asbestos workers), 10 (for smoking non-asbestos workers), and 50 (for smoking asbestos-exposed workers).  Every worker was described with the same set of risk ratios.  Remarkably, and unscientifically, Dr. Epstein gave the same risk figures in every plaintiff’s lung cancer case, regardless of the duration or level of exposure.  In mesothelioma cases, Dr. Epstein took the unscientific position that all fiber types (chrysotile, amosite, crocidolite, and anthopyllite) contributed to any patient’s mesothelioma.

Dr. Epstein’s views made him off limits to plaintiffs in non-malignancy cases, and off limits to defendants in lung cancer and mesothelioma cases.

Because of his careful alignment with both plaintiffs’ and defense bars, Dr. Epstein’s views were never forcefully challenged.  Of course, the Pennsylvania case law in the 1980’s and 1990’s was not particularly favorable to challenges to the validity of opinions about causation, but even as Rule 702 evolved in federal court, both plaintiffs’ and defense counsel were unable to antagonize Dr. Epstein.  The inanity of “each and every exposure” was not seriously hurtful in the early asbestos litigation, when the defendants were almost all manufacturers of asbestos-containing insulation, and if a manufacturer had supplied insulation to a worksite, then the proportion of asbestos exposure for that manufacturer would likely have been “substantial.”

Today, the nature of the asbestos litigation has changed, but it when we examine Pennsylvania law and procedure, it is not surprising to see that Dr. Epstein’s views have had a long-lasting effect.  Claimants with only pleural plaques have been relegated to an “inactive” docket.  Plaintiffs’ expert witnesses still opine that each and every exposure was substantial, without any basis in evidence, and they still recite the same 5x, 10x, and 50x risk ratios, based upon Selikoff’s insulator studies, even though the Philadelphia Court of Common Pleas probably has not seen more than a handful of insulators’ cases in the last decade.  Dozens of epidemiologic studies have shown that asbestos exposures of bystander trades, chrysotile factory workers, and other non-insulator, occupational exposures have lower risks of asbestos-related diseases.

The failure to challenge the Selikoff risk ratios is regrettable, especially considering that it was based upon politics, personalities, and not on scientific or legal evidentiary grounds.

As Irving Selikoff observed about his frequently cited statistics:

“These particular figures apply to the particular groups of asbestos workers in this study.  The net synergistic effect would not have been the same if their smoking habits had been different; and it probably would have been different if their lapsed time from first exposure to asbestos dust had been different or if the amount of asbestos dust they had inhaled had been different.”

E. Cuyler Hammond, Irving Selikoff, and Herbert Seidman, “Asbestos Exposure, Cigarette Smoking and Death Rates,” 330 Ann. N.Y. Acad. Sci. 473, 487 (1979).

The Selikoff risk figures were unreliable even for insulators, given that the so-called non-smokers were admittedly occasional smokers, and the low relative risk for smokers in the general population came from an historical cohort of relatively healthy American Cancer Society volunteers. The updated risk figures for smokers in the general population placed their lung cancer risk closer to, and above, 20-fold, which raised doubts about Selikoff’s neat multiplicative theory.

The more important lesson though is that the Philadelphia courts, with acquiescence from most defense counsel, never challenged the use of Selikoff’s 5x, 10x, and 50x risk ratios to describe asbestos effects and smoking interactions.  Dr. Epstein made such a challenge impolitic and imprudent.  In Philadelphia, the Selikoff risk ratios gained a measure of respectability that they never deserved in science, or in the courtroom.

*****

Under Rule 702, the law has evolved to require reasonable exposure assessments of plaintiffs’ exposures, and supporting epidemiology that shows relevant increase risks at the level and the latency actual experienced by each plaintiff.  This criterion does not come from a “sufficiency” review as some have suggested; it is clearly a requirement of external validity of the epidemiologic studies relied upon by expert witnesses.

The following cases excluded or limited expert witness opinion testimony with respect to epidemiological studies that the court concluded were not sufficiently similar to the facts of the case to warrant the admission of an expert’s opinion based on their results:

SUPREME COURT

General Electric Co. v. Joiner, 522 U.S. 136 (1997)(questioning the external validity of a study of massive injected doses of PCBs in baby mice, with an outcome unrelated to the cancer claimed by paintiff)

1st Circuit

Sutera v. Perrier Group of America Inc., 986 F. Supp. 655 (D. Mass. 1997)(occupational epidemiology of benzene exposure and benzene does not inform health effects from vanishingly low exposure to benzene in bottled water)

Whiting v. Boston Edison Co., 891 F. Supp. 12 (D. Mass. 1995) (excluding plaintiff’s expert witnesses; holding that epidemiology of Japanese atom bomb victims, and of patients treated with X-rays for spinal arthritis, and acute lymphocytic leukemia (ALL), was an invalid extrapolative model for plaintiff’s much lower exposure)

2d Circuit

Wills v. Amerada Hess Corp., 2002 WL 140542 (S.D. N.Y. 2002)(excluding plaintiff’s expert witness who attempted to avoid exposure assessment by arguing no threshold)(‘‘[E]ven though benzene and PAHs have been shown to cause some types of cancer, it is too difficult a leap to allow testimony that says any amount of exposure to these toxins caused squamous cell carcinoma of the head and neck in the decedent… . It is not grounded in reliable scientific methods, but only Dr. Bidanset’s presumptions. It fails all of the Daubert factors.’’), aff’d, 379 F.3d 32 (2d Cir. 2004)(Sotomayor, J.), cert. denied, 126 S.Ct. 355 (2005)

Amorgianos v. National RR Passenger Corp., 137 F. Supp. 2d 147 (E.D. N.Y. 2001), aff’d, 303 F.3d 256 (2d Cir. 2002);

Mancuso v. Consolidated Edison Co., 967 F.Supp. 1437, 1444 (S.D.N.Y. 1997)

3d Circuit

Magistrini v. One Hour Martinizing Dry Cleaning, 180 F. Supp. 2d 584(D.N.J. 2002), aff’d, 68 Fed. Appx. 356 (3d Cir. 2003);

In re W.R. Grace & Co., 355 B.R. 462 (Bankr. D. Del. 2006)

4th Circuit

White v. Dow Chemical Co., 321 F.Appx. 266, 273 (4th Cir. 2009)

Newman v. Motorola, Inc., 78 Fed. Appx. 292 (4th Cir. 2003)

Cavallo v. Star Enterprise, 892 F. Supp. 756, 764, 773 (E.D. Va. 1995) (excluding opinion of expert witness who failed to identify plaintiff ’s exposure levels to jet fuel, and failed to characterize the relevant dose-response relationship), aff’d in relevant part, 100 F.3d 1150, 1159 (4th Cir. 1996)

5th Circuit

LeBlanc v. Chevron USA, Inc., 396 Fed. Appx. 94 (5th Cir. 2010)

 Knight v. Kirby Inland Marine Inc.,482 F.3d 347 (5th Cir. 2007);

Cotroneo v. Shaw Environmental & Infrastructure, Inc., 2007 WL 3145791 (S.D. Tex. 2007)

Castellow v. Chevron USA, 97 F. Supp. 2d 780, 796 (S.D. Tex. 2000) (‘‘[T]here is no reliable evidence before this court on the amount of benzene, from gasoline or any other source, to which Mr. Castellow was exposed.’’)

Moore v. Ashland Chemical Inc., 151 F.3d 269, 278 (5th Cir. 1998) (en banc);

Allen v. Pennsylvania Engineering Corp., 102 F.3d 194, 198-99 (5th Cir. 1996)

6th Circuit

Pluck v. BP Oil Pipeline Co., 640 F.3d 671 (6th Cir. 2011)(affirming district court’s exclusion of Dr. James Dahlgren; noting that he lacked reliable data to support his conclusion of heavy benzene exposure; holding that without quantifiable exposure data, the Dahlgren’s causation opinion was mere “speculation and conjecture”)

 Nelson v. Tennessee Gas Pipeline Co., 243 F.3d 244, 252 (6th Cir. 2001)(noting ‘‘with respect to the question of dose, plaintiffs cannot dispute that [their expert] made no attempt to determine what amount of PCB exposure the Lobelvill subjects had received and simply assumed that it was sufficient to make them ill.’’)

Conde v. Velsicol Chemical Corp., 24 F.3d, 809, 810 (6th Cir. 1994)(excluding expert testimony that chlordane,although an acknowledged carcinogen that was applied in a manner that violated federal criminal law, caused plaintiff’s injuries when expert witness’s opinion was based upon high-dose animal studies as opposed to the low-exposure levels experienced by the plaintiffs)

7th Circuit

Cunningham v. Masterwear Corp., 2007 WL 1164832 (S.D. Ind., Apr. 19, 2007)(excluding plaintiff’s expert witnesses who opined without valid evidence of plaintiffs’ exposure to perchloroethylene (PCE)), aff’d, 569 F.3d 673 (7th Cir. 2009) (Posner, J.)(affirming exclusion of expert witness and grant of summary judgment)

Wintz v. Northrop Corp., 110 F.3d 508, 513 (7th Cir. 1997)

Schmaltz v. Norfolk & Western Ry. Co., 878 F. Supp. 1119, 1122 (N.D. Ill. 1995) (excluding expert witness opinion testimony that was offered in ignorance of plaintiff’s level of exposure to herbicide)

8th Circuit

Junk v. Terminix Intern. Co. Ltd. Partnership, 594 F. Supp. 2d 1062, 1073 (S.D. Iowa 2008).

Medalen v. Tiger Drylac U.S.A., Inc., 269 F. Supp. 2d 1118, 1132 (D. Minn. 2003)

National Bank of Commerce v. Associated Milk Producers, Inc., 22 F. Supp. 2d 942 (E.D. Ark. 1998)(excluding causation opinion that lacked exposure level data), aff’d, 191 F.3d 858 (8th Cir. 1999)

Bednar v. Bassett Furniture Mfg. Co., Inc.,147 F.3d 737, 740 (8th Cir. 1998) (“The Bednars had to make a threshold showing that the dresser exposed the baby to levels of gaseous formaldehyde known to cause the type of injuries she suffered”)

Wright v. Willamette Industries, Inc., 91 F.3d 1105, 1106 (8th Cir. 1996) (affirming exclusion; requiring evidence of actual exposure to levels of substance known to cause claimed injury)

National Bank of Commerce v. Dow Chemical Co., 965 F. Supp. 1490, 1502 (E.D. Ark., 1996)

9th Circuit

In re Bextra & Celebrex Marketing Sales Practices & Product Liab. Litig., 524 F. Supp. 2d 1166, 1180 (N.D. Cal. 2007)(granting Rule 702 exclusion of expert witness’s opinions with respect to low dose, but admitting opinions with respect to high dose Bextra and Celebrex)

Henricksen v. ConocoPhillips Co., 605 F. Supp. 2d 1142, 1157 (E.D. Wash. 2009)

Valentine v. Pioneer Chlor Alkali Co., Inc., 921 F. Supp. 666, 676 (D. Nev. 1996)

Abuan v. General Electric Co., 329 F.3d 329, 333 (9th Cir. 1993) (Guam)

10th Circuit

Maddy v. Vulcan Materials Co., 737 F.Supp. 1528, 1533 (D.Kan. 1990) (noting the lack of any scientific evidence of the level or duration of plaintiff’s exposure to specific toxins).

Estate of Mitchell v. Gencorp, Inc., 968 F. Supp. 592, 600 (D. Kan. 1997), aff’d,165 F.3d 778, 781 (10th Cir. 1999)

11th Circuit

Brooks v. Ingram Barge Co., 2008 WL 5070243 *5 (N.D. Miss. 2008)) (noting that plaintiff’s expert witness “acknowledges that it is unclear how much exhaust Brooks was exposed to, how much exhaust it takes to make developing cancer a probability, or how much other factors played a role in Brooks developing cancer.”)

Cuevas v. E.I. DuPont de Nemours & Co., 956 F. Supp. 1306, 1312 (S.D. Miss. 1997)

Chikovsky v. Ortho Pharmaceutical Corp., 832 F. Supp. 341, 345–46 (S.D. Fla. 1993)(excluding opinion of an expert witness who did not know plaintiff’s actual exposure or dose of Retin-A, and the level of absorbed Retin-A that is unsafe for gestating women)

Savage v. Union Pacific RR, 67 F. Supp. 2d 1021 (E.D. Ark. 1999)

 

STATE CASES

California

Jones v. Ortho Pharmaceutical Corp., 163 Cal. App. 3d 396, 404, 209 Cal. Rptr. 456, 461 (1985)(duration of use in relied upon studies not relevant to plaintiffs’ use)

Michigan

Nelson v. American Sterilizer Co., 566 N.W. 2d 671 (Mich. Ct. App. 1997)(affirming exclusion of expert witness who opined, based upon high-dose animal studies, that plaintiff’s liver disease was caused by low-level exposure to chemicals used in sterilizing medical equipment)

Mississippi

Watts v. Radiator Specialty Co., 2008 WL 2372694 *3 (Miss.2008);

Ohio

Valentine v. PPG Indus., Inc., 158 Ohio App. 3d 615, 821 N.E.2d 580 (2004)

Oklahoma

Christian v. Gray, 2003 Okla. 10, 65 P.3d 591, 601 (2003);

Holstine v. Texasco, 2001 WL 605137 (Okla. Dist. Ct. 2001)(excluding expert witness testimony that failed to assess plaintiff’s short-term, low-level benzene exposure as fitting the epidemiology relied upon to link plaintiff’s claimed injury with his exposure)

Texas

Merrell Dow Pharm., Inc. v. Havner, 953 S.W.2d 706, 720 (Tex. 1997) (“To raise a fact issue on causation and thus to survive legal sufficiency review, a claimant must do more than simply introduce into evidence epidemiological studies that show a substantially elevated risk. A claimant must show that he or she is similar to those in the studies.”).

Merck & Co. v. Garza, 347 S.W.3d 256 (Tex. 2011)

Frias v. Atlantic Richfield Co., 104 S.W.3d 925, 929 (Tex. App. Houston 2003)(holding that plaintiffs’ expert witness’s testimony was inadmissible for relying upon epidemiologic studies that involved much higher levels of exposure than experienced by plaintiff)

Daniels v. Lyondell-Citgo Refining Co, 99 S.W.3d 722 (Tex. App. 2003) (claim that benzene exposure caused plaintiff’s lung cancer had to be supported with studies of comparable exposure, and latency, as that observed and reported in the studies)

Austin v. Kerr-McGee Refining Corp., 25 S.W.3d 280, 292 (Tex. App. Texarkana 2000)

Giving Rule 703 the Cold Shoulder

May 12th, 2012

I have written previously about the gap in Rule 702, which provides a multi-factorial test for the admissibility of an opinion from a properly qualified expert witness:

(a) the expert’s scientific, technical, or other specialized knowledge will help the trier of fact to understand the evidence or to determine a fact in issue;

(b) the testimony is based on sufficient facts or data;

(c) the testimony is the product of reliable principles and methods; and

(d) the expert has reliably applied the principles and methods to the facts of the case.

Noticeably absent from Rule 702 is any requirement that the facts or data upon which the expert witness relies be worth a damn.  From Rule 702(b), (c), and (d) alone, an expert witness, armed with sufficient unreliable, fraudulent, imaginary, or simply incorrect facts and data, using reliable principles and methods, and applying those principles and methods reliably to the facts of the case, gets to testify at trial.  Arguably, the first subsection, Rule 702(a), which limits testimony to helpful “knowledge” provides an overriding condition that helps to qualify the next three.  It is difficult to imagine that knowledge is based upon unreliable facts and data.

Still, the failure to require reliable data explicitly within the scope of Rule 702 is disturbing.  This unhappy state of affairs, in which courts do not exercise gatekeeping over the quality of the data themselves, is apparently the law of the Tenth Circuit, of the United States Court of Appeals.

In Pritchett v. I-Flow Corporation, the plaintiff had shoulder surgery, which required the use of a “pain pump” to inject anesthetic medication into the shoulder post-operatively.  The plaintiff went on to develop “chondrolysis” in his shoulder joint, a condition that involves partial or complete loss of cartilage in the shoulder joint.  Pritchett v. I-Flow Corp., Civil Action No. 09-cv-02433-WJM-KLM. (D. Colo. April 17, 2012) (Mix, J., Magistrate Judge).

The opinion is a mechanical recitation of Daubert procedure and method, with little analysis of the expert witness’s opinion, until the magistrate judge describes the requirement of Rule 702 (b) for “sufficient facts and data”:

“i. Sufficient Facts and Data

The proponent of the opinion must first show that the witness gathered “sufficient facts and data” to formulate the opinion. In the Tenth Circuit, assessment of the sufficiency of the facts and data used by the witness is a quantitative, rather than a qualitative, analysis. Fed. R. Evid. 702, Advisory Committee Notes to 2000 Amendments; see also United States v. Lauder, 409 F.3d 1254, 1264 n.5 (10th Cir. 2005). That is to say, the Court does not examine whether the facts obtained by the witness are themselves reliable; whether the facts used are qualitatively reliable is a question of the weight that should be given to the opinion by the fact-finder, not the admissibility of the opinion. Lauder, 409 F.3d at 1264. Instead, “this inquiry examines only whether the witness obtained the amount of data that the methodology itself demands.” Crabbe, 556 F. Supp. 2d at 1223.”

Pritchett v. I-Flow Corp. (emphasis added).  That is to say: the whole gatekeeping enterprise is really about appearances and not about trying to ensure more accurate fact finding.

If the court’s analysis of Rule 702 should be correct, it is in any event an incomplete analysis that omits the important role of Rule 703:

Rule 703. Bases of an Expert’s Opinion Testimony

An expert may base an opinion on facts or data in the case that the expert has been made aware of or personally observed. If experts in the particular field would reasonably rely on those kinds of facts or data in forming an opinion on the subject, they need not be admissible for the opinion to be admitted. But if the facts or data would otherwise be inadmissible, the proponent of the opinion may disclose them to the jury only if their probative value in helping the jury evaluate the opinion substantially outweighs their prejudicial effect.

According to Magistrate Mix, the reliability of the facts and data do not count for gatekeeping.  Chalk up another loophole to the law’s requirement of reliable scientific evidence.

 

Litigation Funding

May 8th, 2012

An internet search on the phrase “litigation funding” returns thousands of hits.  There are an incredible number of companies and persons “out there” who will buy equity shares in a lawsuit.  Hedge funds are actively seeking opportunities to invest in lawsuits.

Putting aside the concerns about champerty and maintenance, I wonder whether defense counsel are doing enough to work on this issue in trials.  Assuming that these websites really are engaged in the practice they describe, shouldn’t defense counsel include questions related to investments in lawsuits, in their voir dire of the jury panel?

Obviously if potential jurors owned stock in the defendant company, they would be disqualified.  Equity ownership in a chose in action surely is relevant to counsel’s evaluation of a prospective juror’s impartiality.  Even if the prospective juror is not invested in this particular lawsuit, the question is important.  If the investment is in the litigation generally, or in other plaintiffs’ cases within the same litigation, then a jury verdict in favor of the plaintiff would likely benefit the juror by increasing the settlement value of the other cases.  Even investments in unrelated personal injury litigation, the investments have the potential to prejudice the juror against the defense.  For instance, if the juror has investments in another personal injury litigation, returning a large verdict in the present case could benefit the investment by making the company defending against the juror’s chose in action believe that trying cases in the particular venue was too dangerous to risk, and those claims should be settled.

Certainly, the existence and extent of investment by others in a lawsuit should be a worthy line of discovery to conduct in mass tort litigation.

Are we doing enough to stop this insanity?

Haack Attack on Legal Probabilism

May 6th, 2012

Last year, Professor Susan Haack presented a lecture on “legal probabilism,” at a conference on Standards of Proof and Scientific Evidence, held at the University of Girona, in Spain.  The lecture can be viewed on-line, and a manuscript of Haack’s paper is available , as well.  Susan Haack, “Legal Probabilism:  An Epistemological Dissent” (2011)(cited here as “Haack”).   Professor Haack has franked her paper as a draft, with an admonition “do not cite without permission,” an imperative that has no moral or legal force.  Her imperative certainly has no epistemic warrant.  We will ignore it.

As I have noted previously, here and there, Professor Haack is a Professor of philosophy and of law, at the University of Miami, Florida.  She has written widely on the philosophy of science, in the spirit of Peirce’s pragmatism.  Despite her frequent untutored judgments about legal matters, much of what she has written is a useful corrective to formalistic writings on “the scientific method,” and are worthy of study by lawyers interested in the intersection of science and the law.

The video of Professor Haack’s presentation is worth watching to get an idea of how ad hominem her style is.  I won’t repeat her aspersions and pejorative comments here.  They are not in her paper, and I will take her paper, which she posted online, as the expression of her mature thinking.

Invoking Lord Russell and Richard von Mises, Haack criticizes the reduction of epistemology to a calculus of probability.  Russell, for instance, cautioned against confusing the credibility of a claim with the probability that the claim is true:

“[I]t is clear that some things are almost certain, while others are matters of hazardous conjecture. For a rational man, there is a scale of doubtfulness, from simple logical and arithmetical propositions and perceptive judgments, at one end, to such questions as what language the Myceneans spoke or “what song the Sirens sang” at the other … , [T]he rational man, who attaches to each proposition the right degree of credibility, will be guided by the mathematical theory of probability when it is applicable . … The concept ‘degree of credibility’, however, is applicable much more widely than that of mathematical probability.”‘

Bertrand Russell, Human Knowledge, Its Scope and Limits 381 (N.Y. 1948)(quoted in Haack, supra, at 1).   Haack argues that ordinary language is beguiling.  We use “probably” to hedge our commitment to the truth of a prediction or a proposition of fact.  We insert the adverb “probably” to recognize that our statement might turn out false, although we have no idea of how likely, and no way of quantifying the probability of error.  Thus,

“[w]e commonly use the language of probability or likelihood when we talk about the credibility or warrant of a claim-about how likely is it, given this evidence, that the claim is true, or, unconditionally, about how probable the claim is.”

Haack at 14.

Epistemology is the “thing,” and psychology, not.  Haack admits that legal language is inconsistent:  sometimes the law appears to embrace psychological states of mind as relevant criteria for decisions; sometimes the law is expressly looking at epistemic warrant for the truth of claim.  Flipping the philosophical bird to Derrida and Feyerabend, Haack argues that trials are searches for the truth, and that our notions of substantial justice require replacement of psychological standards of proof, to the extent that they are merely subjective and non-epistemic, with a clear theory of epistemic warrant.  Haack at 6 (citing Tehan v. United States, 383 U.S. 406,416 (1966)(“the purpose of a trial is to determine the truth”); id. at 7 (citing In re Winship, 397 U.S. 358, 368, 370 (1970) (Harlan, J. concurring)(the standard of proof is meant to “instruct the factfinder concerning the degree of confidence our society thinks he should have in the correctness of factual conclusions for a particular type of adjudication.)

Haack points out that there are instances where evidence seems to matter more than subjective state of mind, although the law sometimes equivocates.  She cautions us that “we shouldn’t simply assume, just because the word “probable” or “probability” occurs in legal contexts, that we are dealing with mathematical, rather than epistemological, probabilities.  Haack at 16.  (citing and quoting Thomas Starkie, et al., A Practical Treatise of the Law of Evidence and Digest of Proofs in Civil and Criminal Proceedings vol. I, 579 (Philadelphia 1842)(“That … moral probabilities … could ever be represented by numbers … and thus be subject to numerical analysis,” … “cannot but be regarded as visionary and chimerical.”)  Thus the criminal standard, “beyond a reasonable doubt” seems to be about state of mind, but it is described, at least some of the time, as about the quality and strength of the evidence needed to attain such a state of mind.  The standards of “preponderance of the evidence” and “clear and convincing evidence,” on the other hand, appear to be directly related to the strength of the evidentiary display offered by the party with the burden of proof.

An example that Haack might have used, but did not, is the requirement that an expert witness express an opinion to a “reasonable degree of medical or scientific certainty.”  The law is not particularly concerned about the psychological state of certainty possessed by the witness:  the witness may be a dogmatist with absolute certainty but no epistemic warrant; and that simply will not do.

Of course, the preponderance standard is alternatively expressed as the burden to show the disputed fact is “more likely than not” correct, and that brings us back to explicit probabilisms in the law.  Haack’s argument would be bolstered by acknowledging the work of Professor Kahnemann, who makes the interesting point, at several places, that experts, or for that matter anyone making decisions, are not necessarily expert at determining their level of certainty.  Can someone really say that they believe one set of claims have been shown to be 50.1%, and have an intelligent discussion with another person, who adamantly believes that the claims have been shown to 49.9% true.  Do they resolve their differences by splitting the differences?  Unless we are dealing with an explicit set of frequencies or proportions, the language of probability is metaphorical.

Haack appropriates the term warrant for her epistemiologic theory, but the use seems much older and not novel with Haack.  In any event, Haack sets out her theory of “warrants”:

“(i) How supportive the evidence is; analogue: how well a crossword entry fits with the clue and intersecting completed entries. Evidence may be supportive (positive, favorable), undermining (negative, unfavorable), or neutral (irrelevant) with respect to some conclusion.

(ii) How secure the reasons are, independent of the claim in question; analogue:  how reasonable the competed intersecting entries are, independent of the entry in question. The better the independent security of positive reasons, the more warranted the conclusion, but the better the independent security of negative reasons, the less warranted the conclusion.

(iii) How comprehensive the evidence is, i.e., how much of the relevant evidence it includes; analogue: how much of the crossword has been completed. More comprehensive evidence gives more warrant to a conclusion than less comprehensive evidence does iff the additional evidence is at least as favorable as the rest.”

Haack at 18 (internal citation omitted).  According to Haack, the calculus of probabilities does not help in computing degrees of epistemic warrant.  Id. at 20. Her reasons are noteworthy:

  • “since quality of evidence has several distinct dimensions (supportiveness, independent security, comprehensiveness), and there is no way to rank relative success and failure across these different factors, there is no guarantee even of a linear ordering of degrees of warrant;
  • while the probability of p and the probability of not-p must add up to 1, when there is no evidence, or only very weak evidence, either way, neither p nor not-p may be warranted to any degree; and
  • while the probability of p and q (for independent p and q) is the product of the two, and hence, unless both are 1, less than the probability of either, the warrant of a conjunction may be higher than the warrant of its components”

Id. at 20-21.  The third bullet appears to have been a misfire.  If we were to use Bayes’ theorem, the two pieces of evidence would require sequential adjustments to our posterior odds or probability; we would not multiply the two probabilities directly.

Haack’s attack on legal probabilism blinds her to the reality that sometimes all there is in a legal case is probabilistic evidence.  For instance, in the litigation over claims that asbestos causes colorectal cancer, plaintiffs had only a relative risk statistic to support their desired inference that asbestos had caused their colorectal cancers.  There was no other evidence.  (On general causation, the animal studies failed to find colorectal cancer from asbestos ingestion, and the “weight of evidence” was against an association in any event.)  Nonetheless, Haack cites one case as a triumph of her anti-probabilistic viewpoint:

“Here I am deliberately echoing the words of the Supreme Court of New Jersey in Landrigan, rejecting the idea that epidemiological evidence of a doubling of risk is sufficient to establish specific causation in a toxic-tort case: ‘a relative risk of 2.0 is not so much a password to a finding of causation as one piece of evidence among many’.114 This gets the key epistemological point right.”

Landrigan v. Celotex Corp., 127 N.J. 405, 419, 605 A.2d 1079 (1992).  Well, not really.  Had Haack read the Landrigan decision, including the lower courts’ opinions, she would be aware that there were no other pieces of evidence.  There were no biomarkers, no “fingerprints” of causation; no evidence of Mr. Landrigan’s individual, special vulnerability.  The case went up to the New Jersey Supreme Court, along with a companion case, as a result of directed verdicts.  Caterinicchio v. Pittsburgh Corning Corp., 127 N.J. 428, 605 A.2d 1092 (1992). The plaintiffs had put in their cases and rested; the trial courts were required to assume that the facts were as presented by the plaintiffs.  All the plaintiffs had offered, however, of any possible relevance, was a relative risk statistic.

Haack’s fervent anti-probabilism obscures the utility of probability concepts, especially when probabilities are all we have.   In another jarring example, Haack seems to equate any use of Bayes’ theorem, or any legal analysis that invokes an assessment of probability, with misguided “legal probabilism.”  For instance, Haack writes:

“Mr. Raymond Easton was arrested for a robbery on the basis of a DNA “cold hit”; statistically, the probability was very low that the match between Mr. Easton’s DNA (on file after an arrest for domestic violence) and DNA found at the crime scene was random. But Mr. Easton, who suffered from Parkinson’s disease, was too weak to dress himself or walk more than a few yards-let alone to drive to the crime scene, or to commit the crime.”

Haack at 37 (internal citation omitted).  Bayes’ Theorem, with its requirement of inclusion of a base rate, or prior probability, in the complete analysis provides the complete answer to Haack’s misguided error about DNA cold hits.

 

Philadelphia Plaintiff’s Claims Against Fixodent Prove Toothless

May 2nd, 2012

In Milward, Martyn Smith got a pass from the First Circuit of the U.S. Court of Appeals on his “weight of the evidence” (WOE) approach to formulating an opinion as an expert witness.  Last week, Smith’s WOE did not fare so well.  The Honorable Sandra Mazer Moss, in one of her last rulings as judge presiding over the Philadelphia Court of Common Pleas mass tort program, sprinkled some cheer to dispel WOE in Jacoby v Rite Aid PCCP (Order of April 27, 2012; Opinion of April 12, 2012).

Applying Pennsylvania’s Frye standard, Judge Moss upheld Proctor & Gambles challenge to Dr. Martyn Smith, as well as two other plaintiff expert witnesses, Dr. Ebbing Lautenbach and Dr. Frederick Askari.  The plaintiff, Mr. Mark Jacoby, used Fixodent for six years before he first experienced parasthesias and numbness in his hands and feet.  Jacoby’s expert witnesses claimed that Fixodent contains zinc compounds, which are released upon use, and are absorbed into the blood stream.  Very high zinc levels suppress copper levels, and cause a copper deficiency myeloneuropathy.  Finding that the plaintiffs’ causal claims were toothless in the face of sound science, Judge Moss excluded the reports and proffered testimony of Drs. Smith, Askari, and Lautenbach.

Although Pennsylvania courts follow a Frye standard, Judge Moss followed the lead of a federal judge, who had previously examined the same body of evidence, and who excluded plaintiff’s expert witnesses, under Federal Rule of Evidence 702, in In re Denture Cream Prods. Liab. Litig., 795 F. Supp. 2d 1345 (S.D. Fla. 2011).  Without explication, Judge Moss stated that Judge Altanoga’s reasoning and conclusions, reached under federal law, were “very persuasive” under Frye.  Moss Opinion at 5.  In particular, Judge Moss appeared to be impressed by the lack of baseline incidence data on copper deficiency myeloneuropathy, the lack of exposure-response information, and the lack of risk ratios for any level of use of Fixodent.  Id. at 6 – 10.

Judge Moss accepted at face value Martyn Smith’s claims that WOE can be used to demonstrate causation when no individual study is conclusive.  Her Honor did, however, look more critically at the component parts of Smith’s particular application of WOE in the Jacoby case.  Smith used various steps of extrapolation, dose-response, and differential diagnosis in applying WOE, but these steps were woefully unsound.  Id. at 9.  There was no evidence of how low, and for how long, a person’s copper levels must drop before injury results.  Having attacked Proctor & Gamble’s pharmacokinetic studies, the plaintiffs’ expert witnesses had no basis for inferring levels for any plaintiff.  Furthermore, the plaintiffs’ witnesses had no baseline incidence data, and no risk ratios to apply for any level of exposure to, or use of, defendant’s product.

Predictably, plaintiffs’ invoked the pass that Smith received in Milward, but Judge Moss easily distinguished Milward as having involved baseline rates and risk ratios (even if Smith may have imagined the data to calculate those ratios).

Another plaintiff witness, Dr. Askari, used a method he called the “totality of the evidence” (TOE) approach.  In short, TOE is WOE is NO good, as applied in this case.  Id. at 10 -11.

Finally, another plaintiff’s witness, Dr. Lautenbach applied the Naranjo Adverse Drug Reaction Probability Scale, by which he purported to transmute case reports and case series into a conclusion of causality.  Actually, Lautenbach seems to have claimed that the lack of analytical epidemiologic studies supporting an association between Fixodent and myeloneuropathy did not refute the existence of a causal relationship.  Of course, this lack of evidence hardly supports the causal relationship.  Judge Moss assumed that Lautenbach was actually asserting a causal relationship, but since he was relying upon the same woefully, toefully flawed body of evidence, Her Honor excluded Dr. Lautenbach as well.  Id. at 12.

WOE-fully Inadequate Methodology – An Ipse Dixit By Another Name

May 1st, 2012

Take all the evidence, throw it into the hopper, close your eyes, open your heart, and guess the weight.  You could be a lucky winner!  The weight of the evidence suggests that the weight-of-the-evidence (WOE) method is little more than subjective opinion, but why care if it helps you to get to a verdict?

The scientific community has never been seriously impressed by the so-called weight of the evidence (WOE) approach to determining causality.  The phrase is vague and ambiguous; its use, inconsistent. See, e.g., V. H. Dale, G.R. Biddinger, M.C. Newman, J.T. Oris, G.W. Suter II, T. Thompson, et al., “Enhancing the ecological risk assessment process,” 4 Integrated Envt’l Assess. Management 306 (2008)(“An approach to interpreting lines of evidence and weight of evidence is critically needed for complex assessments, and it would be useful to develop case studies and/or standards of practice for interpreting lines of evidence.”);  Igor Linkov, Drew Loney, Susan M. Cormier, F.Kyle Satterstrom, Todd Bridges, “Weight-of-evidence evaluation in environmental assessment: review of qualitative and quantitative approaches,” 407 Science of Total Env’t 5199–205 (2009); Douglas L. Weed, “Weight of Evidence: A Review of Concept and Methods,” 25 Risk Analysis 1545 (2005) (noting the vague, ambiguous, indefinite nature of the concept of “weight of evidence” review);   R.G. Stahl Jr., “Issues addressed and unaddressed in EPA’s ecological risk guidelines,” 17 Risk Policy Report 35 (1998); (noting that U.S. Environmental Protection Agency’s guidelines for ecological weight-of-evidence approaches to risk assessment fail to provide guidance); Glenn W. Suter II, Susan M. Cormier, “Why and how to combine evidence in environmental assessments:  Weighing evidence and building cases,” 409 Science of the Total Environment 1406, 1406 (2011)(noting arbitrariness and subjectivity of WOE “methodology”).

 

General Electric v. Joiner

Most savvy judges quickly figured out that weight of the evidence (WOE) was suspect methodology, woefully lacking, and indeed, not really a methodology at all.

The WOE method was part of the hand waving in Joiner by plaintiffs’ expert witnesses, including the frequent testifier Rabbi Teitelbaum.  The majority recognized that Rabbi Teitelbaum’s WOE weighed in at less than a peppercorn, and affirmed the district court’s exclusion of his opinions.  The Joiner Court’s assessment provoked a dissent from Justice Stevens, who was troubled by the Court’s undressing of the WOE methodology:

“Dr. Daniel Teitelbaum elaborated on that approach in his deposition testimony: ‘[A]s a toxicologist when I look at a study, I am going to require that that study meet the general criteria for methodology and statistical analysis, but that when all of that data is collected and you ask me as a patient, Doctor, have I got a risk of getting cancer from this? That those studies don’t answer the question, that I have to put them all together in my mind and look at them in relation to everything I know about the substance and everything I know about the exposure and come to a conclusion. I think when I say, “To a reasonable medical probability as a medical toxicologist, this substance was a contributing cause,” … to his cancer, that that is a valid conclusion based on the totality of the evidence presented to me. And I think that that is an appropriate thing for a toxicologist to do, and it has been the basis of diagnosis for several hundred years, anyway’.

* * * *

Unlike the District Court, the Court of Appeals expressly decided that a ‘weight of the evidence’ methodology was scientifically acceptable. To this extent, the Court of Appeals’ opinion is persuasive. It is not intrinsically “unscientific” for experienced professionals to arrive at a conclusion by weighing all available scientific evidence—this is not the sort of ‘junk science’ with which Daubert was concerned. After all, as Joiner points out, the Environmental Protection Agency (EPA) uses the same methodology to assess risks, albeit using a somewhat different threshold than that required in a trial.  Petitioners’ own experts used the same scientific approach as well. And using this methodology, it would seem that an expert could reasonably have concluded that the study of workers at an Italian capacitor plant, coupled with data from Monsanto’s study and other studies, raises an inference that PCB’s promote lung cancer.”

General Electric v. Joiner, 522 U.S. 136, 152-54 (1997)(Stevens, J., dissenting)(internal citations omitted)(confusing critical assessment of studies with WOE; and quoting Rabbit Teitelbaum’s attempt to conflate diagnosis with etiological attribution).  Justice Stevens could reach his assessment only by ignoring the serious lack of internal and external validity in the studies relied upon by Rabbi Teitelbaum.  Those studies did not support his opinion individually or collectively.

Justice Stevens was wrong as well about the claimed scientific adequacy of WOE.  Courts have long understood that precautionary, preventive judgments of regulatory agencies are different from scientific conclusions that are admissible in civil and criminal litigation.  See Allen v. Pennsylvania Engineering Corp., 102 F.3d 194 (5th Cir. 1996)(WOE, although suitable for regulatory risk assessment, is not appropriate in civil litigation).  Justice Stevens’ characterization of WOE was little more than judicial ipse dixit, and it was, in any event, not the law; it was the argument of a dissenter.

 

Milward v. Acuity Specialty Products

Admittedly, dissents can sometimes help lower court judges chart a path of evasion and avoidance of a higher court’s holding.  In Milward, Justice Stevens’ mischaracterization of WOE and scientific method was adopted as the legal standard for expert witness testimony by a panel of the United States Court of Appeals, for the First Circuit.  Milward v. Acuity Specialty Products Group, Inc., 664 F.Supp. 2d 137 (D. Mass. 2009), rev’d, 639 F.3d 11 (1st Cir. 2011), cert. denied, U.S. Steel Corp. v. Milward, ___ U.S. ___, 2012 WL 33303 (2012).

Mr. Milward claimed that he was exposed to benzene as a refrigerator technician, and developed acute promyelocytic leukeumia (APL) as result.  664 F. Supp. 2d at 140. In support of his claim, Mr. Milward offered the testimony of Dr. Martyn T. Smith, a toxicologist, who testified that the “weight of the evidence” supported his opinion that benzene exposure causes APL. Id. Smith, in his litigation report, described his methodology as an application of WOE:

“The term WOE has come to mean not only a determination of the statistical and explanatory power of any individual study (or the combined power of all the studies) but the extent to which different types of studies converge on the hypothesis.) In assessing whether exposure to benzene may cause APL, I have applied the Hill considerations . Nonetheless, application of those factors to a particular causal hypothesis, and the relative weight to assign each of them, is both context dependent and subject to the independent judgment of the scientist reviewing the available body of data. For example, some WOE approaches give higher weight to mechanistic information over epidemiological data.”

Smith Report at ¶¶19, 21 (citing Sheldon Krimsky, “The Weight of Scientific Evidence in Policy and Law,” 95(S1) Am. J. Public Health 5130, 5130-31 (2005))(March 9, 2009).  Smith marshaled several bodies of evidence, which he claimed collectively supported his opinion that benzene causes APL.  Milward, 664 F. Supp. 2d at 143.

Milward also offered the testimony of a philosophy professor, Carl F. Cranor, for the opinion that WOE was an acceptable methodology, and that all scientific inference is subject to judgment.  This is the same Cranor who, advocating for open admissions of all putative scientific opinions, showcased his confusion between statistical significance probability and the posterior probability involved in a conclusion of causality.  Carl F. Cranor, Regulating Toxic Substances: A Philosophy of Science and the Law at 33-34(Oxford 1993)(“One can think of α, β (the chances of type I and type II errors, respectively) and 1- β as measures of the “risk of error” or “standards of proof.”) See also id. at 44, 47, 55, 72-76.

After a four-day evidentiary hearing, the district court found that Martyn Smith’s opinion was merely a plausible hypothesis, and not admissible.  Milward, 664 F. Supp. 2d at 149.  The Court of Appeals, in an opinion by Chief Judge Lynch, however, reversed and ruled that an inference of general causation based on a WOE methodology satisfied the reliability requirement for admission under Federal Rule of Evidence 702.  639 F.3d at 26.  According to the Circuit, WOE methodology was scientifically sound,  Id. at 22-23.

 

WOE Cometh

Because the WOE methodology is not well described, either in the published literature or in Martyn Smith’s litigation report, it is difficult to understand exactly what the First Circuit approved by reversing Smith’s exclusion.  Usually the burden is on the proponent of the opinion testimony, and one would have thought that the vagueness of the described methodology would count against admissibility.  It is hard to escape the conclusion that the Circuit elevated a poorly described method, best characterized as hand waving, into a description of scientific method

The Panel appeared to have been misled by Carl F. Cranor, who described “inference to the best explanation” as requiring a scientist to “consider all of the relevant evidence” and “integrate the evidence using professional judgment to come to a conclusion about the best explanation. Id at 18. The available explanations are then weighed, and a would-be expert witness is free to embrace the one he feels offers the “best” explanation.  The appellate court’s opinion takes WOE, combined with Cranor’s “inference to the best explanation,” to hold that an expert witness need only opine that he has considered the range of plausible explanations for the association, and that he believes that the causal explanation is the best or “most plausible.”  Id. at 20 (upholding this approach as “methodologically reliable”).

What is missing of course is the realization that plausible does not mean established, reasonably certain, or even more likely than not.  The Circuit’s invocation of plausibility also obscures the indeterminacy of the available data for supporting a reliable conclusion of causation in many cases.

Curiously, the Panel likened WOE to the use of differential diagnosis, which is a method for inferring the specific cause of a particular patient’s disease or disorder.  Id. at 18.  This is a serious confusion between a method concerned with general causation and one concerned with specific causation.  Even if, by the principle of charity, we allow that the First Circuit was thinking of some process of differential etiology rather than diagnosis, given that diagnoses (other than for infectious diseases and a few pathognomonic disorders) do not usually carry with them information about unique etiologic agents.  But even such a process of differential etiology is a well-structured dysjunctive syllogism of the form:

A v B v C

~A ∩ ~B

∴ C

There is nothing subjective about assigning weights or drawing inferences in applying such a syllogism.  In the Milward case, one of the propositional facts that might have well explained the available evidence was chance, but plaintiff’s expert witness Smith could not and did not rule out chance in that the studies upon which he relied were not statistically significant.  Smith could thus never get past “therefore” in any syllogism or in any other recognizable process of reasoning.

The Circuit Court provides no insight into the process Smith used to weigh the available evidence, and it failed to address the analytical gaps and evidentiary insufficiencies addressed by the trial court, other than to invoke the mantra that all these issues go to “the weight, not the admissibility” of Smith’s opinions.  This, of course, is a conclusion, not an explanation or a legal theory.

There is also a cute semantic trick lurking in plaintiffs’ position in Milward, which results from their witnesses describing their methodology as “WOE.”  Since the jury is charged with determining the “weight of the evidence,” any evaluation of the WOE would be an invasion of the province of the jury.  Milward, 639 F.3d at 20. QED by the semantic device of deliberating conflating the name of the putative scientific methodology with the term traditionally used to describe jury fact finding.

In any event, the Circuit’s chastisement of the district court for evaluating Smith’s implementation of the WOE methodology, his logical, mathematical, and epidemiological errors, his result-driven reinterpretation of study data, threatens to read an Act of Congress — the Federal Rules of Evidence, and especially Rules 702 and 703 — out of existence by judicial fiat.  The Circuit’s approach is also at odds with Supreme Court precedent (now codified in Rule 702) on the importance and the requirement of evaluating opinion testimony for analytical gaps and the ipse dixit of expert witnesses.  General Electic Co. v. Joiner, 522 U.S. 136, 146 (1997).

 

Smith’s Errors in Recalculating Odds Ratios of Published Studies

In the district court, the defendants presented testimony of an epidemiologist, Dr. David H. Garabrant, who took Smith to task for calculating risk ratios incorrectly.  Smith did not have any particular expertise in epidemiologist, and his faulty calculations were problematic from the perspective of both Rule 702 and Rule 703.  The district court found the criticisms of Smith’s calculations convincing, 664 F. Supp. 2d at 149, but the appellate court held that the technical dispute was for the jury; “both experts’ opinions are supported by evidence and sound scientific reasoning,” Milward, 639 F.3d at 24.  This ruling is incomprehensible.  Plaintiffs had the burden of showing admissibility of Smith opinion generally, but also the reasonability of his reliance upon the calculated odds ratio.  The defendants had no burden of persuasion on the issue of Smith’s calculations, but they presented testimony, which apparently carried the day.  The appellate court had no basis for reversing the specific ruling with respect to the erroneously calculated risk ratio.

 

Smith’s Reliance upon Statistically Insignificant Studies

Smith relied upon studies that were not statistically significant at any accepted level.  An opinion of causality requires a showing that chance, bias, and confounding have been excluded in assessing an existing association.  Smith failed to exclude chance as an explanation for the association, and the burden to make this exclusion was on the plaintiffs. This failure was not something that could readily be patched by adverting to other evidence of studies in animals or in test tubes.    The Court of Appeals excused the important analytical gap in plaintiffs’ witness’s opinion because APL is rare, and data collection is difficult in the United States.  Id. at 24.  Evidence “consistent with” and “suggestive of” the challenged witness’s opinion thus suffices.  This is a remarkable homeopathic dilution of both legal and scientific causation.  Now we have a rule of law that allows plaintiffs to be excused from having to prove their case with reliable evidence if they allege a rare disease for which they lack evidence.

 

Leveling the Hierarchy of Evidence

Imagine trying to bring a medication to market with a small case-control study, with a non-statistically significant odds ratio!  Oh, but these clinical trials are so difficult and expensive; and they take such a long time.  Like a moment’s thought, when thinking is so hard and a moment such a long time.  We would be quite concerned if the FDA abridged the standard for causal efficacy in the licensing of new medications; we should be just as concerned about judicial abridgments of standards for causation of harm in tort actions.

Leveling the hierarchy of evidence has been an explicit or implicit goal of several law professors.  Some of the leveling efforts even show up in the new Reference Manual for Scientific Evidence (RMSE 3d ed. 2011).  SeeNew-Age Levellers – Flattening Hierarchy of Evidence.”

The Circuit, in Milward, quoted an article published in the Journal of the National Cancer Institute by Michele Carbone and others who suggest that there should be no hierarchy, but the Court ignored a huge body of literature that explains and defends the need for recognizing that not all study designs or types are equal.  Interestingly, the RMSE chapter on epidemiology by Professor Green (see more below) cites the same article.  RMSE 3d at 564 & n.48 (citing and quoting symposium paper that “[t]here should be no hierarchy [among different types of scientific methods to determine cancer causation]. Epidemiology, animal, tissue culture and molecular pathology should be seen as integrating evidences in the determination of human carcinogenicity.” Michele Carbone et al., “Modern Criteria to Establish Human Cancer Etiology,” 64 Cancer Res. 5518, 5522 (2004).)  Carbone, of course, is best known for his advocacy of a viral cause (SV40), of human mesothelioma, a claim unsupported, and indeed contradicted, by epidemiologic studies.  Carbone’s statement does not support the RMSE chapter’s leveling of epidemiology and toxicology, and Carbone is, in any event, an unlikely source to cite.

The First Circuit, in Milward, studiously ignored a mountain of literature on evidence-based medicine, including the RSME 3d chapter on “Reference Guide on Medical Testimony,” which teaches that leveling of study designs and types is inappropriate. The RMSE chapter devotes several pages to explaining the role of study design in assessing an etiological issue:

3. Hierarchy of medical evidence

With the explosion of available medical evidence, increased emphasis has been placed on assembling, evaluating, and interpreting medical research evidence.  A fundamental principle of evidence-based medicine (see also Section IV.C.5, infra) is that the strength of medical evidence supporting a therapy or strategy is hierarchical.

When ordered from strongest to weakest, systematic review of randomized trials (meta-analysis) is at the top, followed by single randomized trials, systematic reviews of observational studies, single observational studies, physiological studies, and unsystematic clinical observations.150 An analysis of the frequency with which various study designs are cited by others provides empirical evidence supporting the influence of meta-analysis followed by randomized controlled trials in the medical evidence hierarchy.151 Although they are at the bottom of the evidence hierarchy, unsystematic clinical observations or case reports may be the first signals of adverse events or associations that are later confirmed with larger or controlled epidemiological studies (e.g., aplastic anemia caused by chloramphenicol,152 or lung cancer caused by asbestos153). Nonetheless, subsequent studies may not confirm initial reports (e.g., the putative association between coffee consumption and pancreatic cancer).154

John B. Wong, Lawrence O. Gostin, and Oscar A. Cabrera, “Reference Guide on Medical Testimony,” RMSE 3d 687, 723 -24 (2011).   The implication that there is no hierarchy of evidence in causal inference, and that tissue culture studies are as relevant as epidemiology, is patently absurd. The Circuit not only went out on a limb, it managed to saw the limb off, while “out there.”

 

Milward – Responses Critical and Otherwise

The First Circuit’s decision in Milward made an immediate impression upon those writers who have worked hard to dismantle or marginalize Rule 702.  The Circuit’s decision was mysteriously cited with obvious approval by Professor Margaret Berger, even though she had died before the decision was published!  Margaret A. Berger, “The Admissibility of Expert Testimony,” RMSE 3d at 20 & n. 51(2011).  Professor Michael Green, one of the reporters for the ALI’s Restatement (Third) of Torts hyperbolically called Milward “[o]ne of the most significant toxic tort causation cases in recent memory.”  Michael D. Green, “Introduction: Restatement of Torts as a Crystal Ball,” 37 Wm. Mitchell L. Rev. 993, 1009 n.53 (2011).

The WOE approach, and its embrace in Milward, obscures the reality that sometimes the evidence does not logically or analytically support the offered conclusion, and at other times, the best explanation is uncertainty.  By adopting the WOE approach, vague and ambiguous as it is, the Milward Court was beguiled into holding that WOE determinations are for the jury.  The lack of meaningful content of WOE means that decisions such as Milward effectively remove the gatekeeping function, or permit that function to be minimally satisfied by accepting an expert witness’s claim to have employed WOE.  The epistemic warrant required by Rule 702 is diluted if not destroyed.  Scientific hunch and speculation, proper in their place, can be passed off for scientific knowledge to gullible or result-oriented judges and juries.